Dr Ellie Murray Profile picture
Jul 21, 2018 25 tweets 11 min read Read on X
Wow, #epibookclub, we’re officially halfway through the #bookofwhy!

Chapter 6 is a doozy... we’re going to learn all about paradoxes!! Get ready to have your mind blown!! 🤯🤯🤯
Given last week’s tragic fail on paradox gifs, I made you our very own #epibookclub gif! It’s paradox time!!

(Please be kind this is my very first homemade gif 😂😂)
I like the chapter set up this week: @yudapearl explains importance of spending time working out the paradoxes...they can give us insight into how people process causal information. He says these are paradoxes b/c they straddle the rungs of the #ladderofcausation

So, up we go!
We begin with the Monty Hall problem. I found the data table (Table 6.1) to be really helpful.

For simplicity, whichever door you picked is Door 1.

Here’s Pearl’s table
If you don’t like to read, here’s an emoji version.

It shows the outcome(⁉️) for the 3 possible door (🚪), car (🚗), goat (🐐) combos.

Monty always picks a🚪with a🐐, so we can easily tell from the table if you win (🎉) or lose (😫) by switching(🔄) or staying (⏹)
You’ve only got a 1 in 3 chance of winning if you stick with your original pick, but a 2 in 3 chance of winning if you switch!!

It seems like magic but it’s really because Monty gave you new information!
Monty’s choice is determined by your choice & the location of the car. That makes it a collider!

As we’ve learned, when you include the collider in your analysis, you induce a spurious association!

Here, Monty’s choice opens a path between your choice & the car!
As a second attempt to explain, Pearl introduces a simpler game: what if Monty is *also* guessing randomly?

Now, the location of the car doesn’t affect Monty’s choice, there’s no collider, and you don’t do any better whether you switch or stay!!
So, Monty’s choice only helps if we know how Monty is deciding!

The lesson here? How we obtain information is just as important as the information itself!

Good lesson for #epi, and good lesson for #life
Pearl finishes this section with a third attempt at explaining, using a Bayesian framework:A hypothesis that survives testing gets an updated probability of being true.

When Monty knows where the car is and picks Door 2, then you learn something about Door 2 & 3, but not Door 1
Door 1 wasn’t an option for Monty to pick (you already claimed it!), so you learn nothing about Door 1.

Result: the probability of the car in Door 1 doesn’t change, but for Door 2 & 3 the probability they have the car does change!
When Monty doesn’t know where the car is, picking Door 2 only tells u something about Door 2, so the probability of Doors 1 & 3 don’t change and it doesn’t matter if you switch or not!
That’s all for Monty Hall.

Next up, Berkson’s bias: even if two diseases aren’t related, if you look at people who are hospitalized then you will find an association between them!

Now that we know DAGs, this is simple! Hospitalization is a collider, and restricting opens it up
Pearl gives a couple other examples of collider bias caused by your selection process.

For ex, maybe u only date people who are cute or funny, or both, but never anyone who isn’t cute *and* is boring. Then, among people you date, cute dates are likely boring & vice versa!
Another example: flip 2 coins 100 times each & record only the times when at least 1 coin has heads.

Hypothesis: You’ll get about 75 records, within which the two coins are associated, even tho they are actually independent!!

Explanation: selection is a collider!!
I loved this example, and I think it would make a great Intro Epi lab exercise. So I got myself 2 coins and I did it!

•Among all 100 tosses, the 2 coins were independent (p=0.56).
•Among 73 tosses with 1 or 2 heads, the 2 coins were associated (p=0.000001).
Collider bias‼️
Wanna check the results? Here’s my data (all 100 tosses are included but the code also subsets to 1 or 2 heads), and some very basic R code to compare the two coins.

github.com/eleanormurray/…
A fun and easy way to show how selection can create bias! Another thing I learned? Tossing coins is actually kinda hard!
Finally we get to Simpson’s paradox. It boils down to this: if u have confounding u should look at adjusted results & if u have mediation u should look at unadjusted.

When u don’t know which you have, it can be confusing b/c adjusted & unadjusted could give opposite conclusions
Example 1: a drug fails to prevent heart attacks for men, fails for women, but seems to succeed overall.

Here, gender is most likely a confounder b/c it comes before the drug in time. So, we should adjust. The results for men and women separately are right: drug A doesn’t work!
Example 2: a drug given to lower blood pressure & prevent heart attacks seems not to work within each blood pressure group but does overall.

Here, blood pressure is a mediator and adjusting blocks the effect. The unadjusted results are right: drug B does work!
Finally, we get a version of Simpson’s paradox called Lord’s paradox.

Lord wants to know if children in a school gain weight over the year when a new diet is put in place. He looks at boys and girls separately comparing weight change by gender & sees no difference.
But then he looks within levels of September (baseline) weight, and suddenly there’s a difference!

What’s going on?

The causal q here is (weirdly) does gender cause weight gain. The first analysis is the right one to do because there is no confounding!
If Lord had changed the example slightly to compare two diets instead of genders, now the situation is reversed!

Baseline weight *might* be a confounder for diet choice &if so, the adjusted analysis is correct!

(But if diet were randomized, unadjusted is still the way to go!)
This was a pretty intense chapter. I’m very curious to hear whether you understood it, especially if this is your first real foray into #causalinference.

Share your comments, questions, confusions, etc!

Which bias is the most 🤯🤯?

• • •

Missing some Tweet in this thread? You can try to force a refresh
 

Keep Current with Dr Ellie Murray

Dr Ellie Murray Profile picture

Stay in touch and get notified when new unrolls are available from this author!

Read all threads

This Thread may be Removed Anytime!

PDF

Twitter may remove this content at anytime! Save it as PDF for later use!

Try unrolling a thread yourself!

how to unroll video
  1. Follow @ThreadReaderApp to mention us!

  2. From a Twitter thread mention us with a keyword "unroll"
@threadreaderapp unroll

Practice here first or read more on our help page!

More from @EpiEllie

Sep 16, 2018
Interested in thinking more deeply about what a “cause” is? Causation: A Very Short Introduction from @ranilillanjum and @SDMumford is a great starting point.

Thread recap starting now👇🏽#twittereview #epibookclub #causation #causalinference #epimethodsclub
Chapter 1 sets up the problem: causation is hard to define, both in general & for specific events. It’s more than just temporal ordering, but is it a separate thing?

An ex., a town gets sick after flood of rats. Did the rats cause sickness? Maybe it was actually a sick visitor.
Chapter 2 introduces us to Hume’s theories of causation.

1st, regularity: sometimes things are *regularly* followed by other things.

Is this causation? If so, how regular is regular enough? How many times do we have to observe steam after heating water to say it’s causal?
Read 23 tweets
Sep 1, 2018
Now that the #epibookclub is over, my weekends are free for reading #RCTs. So, how about a #tweetorial about #pragmatic trials, causal questions, and #landmark analyses, inspired by the #SCOTHEART trial?

#epimethodsclub #cardiotwitter
If we’re going to talk about #pragmatic trials, then we need to start with a definition. The simplest definition I’ve seen is from a trialist I interviewed for my recent @JClinEpi paper (authors.elsevier.com/a/1XS1b3BcJPuv…)

pRCTs “...attempt to address effectiveness in real world settings”
Sure, it’s a bit vague but it’s useful because, like Tolstoy’s unhappy families, #pragmatic trials are all different.

So, what makes me think #SCOTHEART is pragmatic?

My 2¢: lack of blinding, inclusion criteria based on symptoms not diagnoses, & standard care as comparator.
Read 20 tweets

Did Thread Reader help you today?

Support us! We are indie developers!


This site is made by just two indie developers on a laptop doing marketing, support and development! Read more about the story.

Become a Premium Member ($3/month or $30/year) and get exclusive features!

Become Premium

Don't want to be a Premium member but still want to support us?

Make a small donation by buying us coffee ($5) or help with server cost ($10)

Donate via Paypal

Or Donate anonymously using crypto!

Ethereum

0xfe58350B80634f60Fa6Dc149a72b4DFbc17D341E copy

Bitcoin

3ATGMxNzCUFzxpMCHL5sWSt4DVtS8UqXpi copy

Thank you for your support!

Follow Us!

:(